Ubuntu is an African word for

Before we start

This was again a presentation for the Best mathematics club in the multiverse. It is meant for both younger and older students, as well as working mathematicians. Its objective therefore lied in breadth rather than depth. I removed lots of topics I wanted to talk about, as the talk I gave got too long. It is not a scientific talk. Comments and corrections are welcome.

Why well-orderings?

Why are well-orderings the backbone of mathematics? A similar claim for Zermelo-Fraenckel-Set-Theory (ZFC) was made by Oliver Deiser in his book Einführung in die Mengenlehre, about the constructible cardinal numbers. In ZFC, cardinal numbers are specific ordinal numbers, and ordinal numbers are sets which are well-ordered by the \in-Relation (roughly speaking). And in fact, the study of well-orderings is an important part of set theory. In recursion theory, well-orderings and well-quasi-orderings can be used for termination proofs, and are also important for newer foundational systems that base on type theory. In proof theory, well-orderings can measure the consistency strength of a theory. The axiom of choice is closely related to well-orderings, and it is an important principal in classical mathematics, specifically analysis, stochastics and topology.

A short definition

Definition. In short, a well-ordering is a linear ordering relation with no infinite descending chains.

That is, if we have some collection of objects ("Set") A, and a binary relation <_A on this collection, then the pair (A,<_A) is a well-ordering, if it satisfies:

  • linearity: \forall_{a,b\in A}. a <_A b \vee a = b \vee b <_A
   a.
  • irreflexivity: \forall_{a\in A}.\neg a <_A a
  • transitivity: \forall_{a,b,c\in A}. a <_A b \rightarrow b
   <_A c \rightarrow a <_A c
  • well-foundedness: Let B\subseteq A and B\neq\emptyset. Then B has a <_A-minimal element.

We write a >_A b for b <_A a, and a \le_A b for a <_A b \vee a = b and a \ge_A b for b \ge_A
a. In most cases it is clear from the context which relation we mean, so we shall leave the index out and write < instead of <_A, etc. We often just write A instead of (A,
<_A) if the ordering we mean is clear (or no specific order is given).

Canonical examples for well-orderings are the default ordering on \mathbb{N}_0, and on all its subsets – especially also all of its finite subsets, and the empty set (no axiom sais that there has to be an element at all).

Exercise: Show that if < is a well-ordering, then \le is reflexive, transitive, antisymmetric (\forall_{a,b}.a\le b\rightarrow b\le a\rightarrow a=b) and every decreasing sequence is stationary.

Definition: We call orderings which are reflexive, transitive, antisymmetric, and in which every decreasing sequence is stationary, weak well-orderings.

Most people have probably heard of the concepts of homomorphism and isomorphosm. The idea is that, given two structures, there is a "renaming" between these structures that preserves the structure fully or partially.

Definition: Let A and B be well-orderings, and f:A\rightarrow B, such that \forall_{a_1,a_2\in A}. a_1
  <_A a_2 \rightarrow f(a_1) <_B f(a_2). Then f is called a homomorphism. A bijective homomorphism is called isomorphism.

(Notice that by definition, every homomorphism is injective.)

Let us define [n]:=\{m\in\mathbb{N}_0\mid m<n\}, with the canonical ordering on it.

Lemma: For all m,n\in\mathbb{N}_0, m\le n if and only if there exists a homomorphism f : [m]\rightarrow[n].

Proof. "\Rightarrow": Just set f x =
x. "\Leftarrow": This is an instance of the well-known Pigeonhole principle.

Lemma: Every finite subset X\subset\mathbb{N}_0 with n elements is isomorphic to [n].

Proof. By induction. For n=0 this follows from extensionality. As step, notice that X is non-empty, and therefore has a minimal element, say x. By induction, there is an isomorphism f : [n-1] \rightarrow X\backslash\{x\}. Then trivially, gz:=\left\{\begin{array}{cl} x & \mbox{ for } z = n \\ f
z & \mbox{ otherwise}\end{array}\right. is an isomorphism.

Lemma: Every infinite subset X\subseteq\mathbb{N}_0 is isomorphic to \mathbb{N}.

Proof. Let us define


\left<n\right>:=\left\{
\begin{array}{rl}
\emptyset & \mbox{ for } n = 0 \\
\left<n-1\right>\cup\min(X\backslash\left<n-1\right>) & \mbox{ otherwise }\end{array}\right.

From our previous lemma, we get isomorphisms f_n:\left<n\right>\rightarrow[n]. Notice that the graphs G_n=\{(x,y)\mid f_n x=y\} of these isomorphisms are strictly increasing, that is, G_0\subsetneq G_1\subsetneq
G_2\subsetneq\ldots. Therefore, we can define G_\omega:=\bigcup_i G_i, and this must be the graph of a bijective function f_\omega:X\rightarrow\mathbb{N}.

Lemma: Induction is equivalent to well-ordering on \mathbb{N}.

Proof. "\Rightarrow": Let X\subseteq\mathbb{N}, and X\neq\emptyset. Then there is some n\in X. We do induction on n. For n = 0, n is trivially minimal. Now in the step, if we already know that all sets containing a number < n have a minimum, and n\in X, either n is already the minimum of X, or X contains a smaller element. "\Leftarrow": Assume there was some set X such that 0\in X, X+1\subseteq X but X\neq\mathbb{N}. Then there is some minimal element in n\in\mathbb{N}\backslash X. Trivially, n\neq 0 and n-1\not\in X. Contradiction.

Side Note: This lemma is related to Markov's Principle, which is a theorem about intuitionistic logic. It is an example for a theorem which holds for every instance, but is not provable in general.

Exercise: If this is new to you: Before you read on, can you think of infinite well-orderings which are not isomorphic to \mathbb{N}?

Solution. Of course, there is no unique solution to this. One simple example is the canonical ordering on \{\lim_{m\rightarrow n}(1 -
\frac{1}{m})\mid n\in\mathbb{N}_0\}. Essentially, it is almost the same as \mathbb{N}, with one exception: 1 is larger than all other elements.

Comparing and combining well-orderings

Something very common in mathematics is to view structures "up to isomorphism". For example, one talks about the "Field F_2", even though in the common mathematical theories it is not unique. We will do the same with well-orderings now: We identify isomorphic well-orderings. Therefore, we can say, all finite well-orderings are given by [0],[1],[2],\ldots. We already began comparing finite well-orderings by their homomorphisms, and we will just continue doing so by saying, a well-ordering a is less-than-or-equal a well-ordering b, written a\le b, if there is a homomorphism a\rightarrow b. Then, we go even further, and leave out the squared brackets, that is, we write 0,1,2,\ldots for the finite well-orderings.

We have already seen that the smallest infinite well-ordering is the canonical ordering on \mathbb{N}, which we will call \omega.

Lemma: Let (x, <) be a well-ordering, and y\in
  x. Then (\{z\in x\mid z<y\}, <) is also a well-ordering which is not isomorphic to (x, <).

Proof. Trivially, (\{z\in x\mid z<y\},<) is also a well-ordering. Assuming there was an isomorphism f:\{z\in x\mid
 z<y\}\rightarrow x, then \{z\in x\mid f(z)\neq z\} is non-empty and contains a smallest element m such that f(m)\neq m. Then there must be some n\in x such that f(n)=m, but as m was minimal and n\neq m, we know that n>m, therefore f(n)>f(m), so m>f(m), which means that f(f(m))=f(m) since m was minimal, and therefore f(m)>f(f(m))=f(m). Contradiction.

Lemma and Definition: For every two well-orderings a,b, the sum a+b is defined as the disjoint union of a and b with the ordering that makes every element of a smaller than every element of b. a+b is a well-ordering.

Proof. Exercise.

Notice: The addition of well-orderings is not commutative. 1+\omega=\omega, while \omega+1 is the well-ordering in our above example.

Lemma and Definition: For every two well-orderings a,b, the product a\cdot b is the lexicographical ordering on a\times b: (a_1, b_1) < (a_2, b_2) :\Leftrightarrow
  a_1<a_2\vee(a_1=a_2\wedge b_1<b_2).

Notice: The product of well-orderings is not commutative. 2\cdot\omega=\omega, but \omega\cdot
  2=\omega + \omega.

Notice: The finite well-orderings with addition and multiplication are essentially \mathbb{N}.

Well-orderings in set theory

While currently, in the realm of logic, there are new tools being built to cope with this problem, for well-orderings the problem has been solved in an elegant way inside set theory, which is currently the one which is most well developed.

Ordinal Numbers

Definition: A set x is called an ordinal number if for all y\in x we have y\subseteq x and x is well-ordered by \in. The class of all ordinals is called On.

Lemma: \emptyset\in x for x\in On.

Proof. x contains a minimum y. Assume there was some z\in
 y, then also z\in x, and y would not be minimal anymore. Contradiction. Thus, y=\emptyset.

Lemma: If y\in x and x\in On, then y\in On.

Proof. As y\in x, also y\subseteq x, so trivially, y is well-ordered by \in. Assuming z\in y and t\in z, by transitivity we have t\in y, so every element of y is a subset. y\in On.

Theorem: If x and y are ordinals whose well-orderings regarding \in are isomorphic, then x=y.

Proof. Call the isomorphism f. Assuming f\neq id, there must be a minimal z\in x such that f(z)\neq
 z. Trivially, f(\emptyset)=\emptyset, so z\neq\emptyset. Therefore, there is some t\in
 z. Trivially, we have f(z)=\{f(t)\mid t\in z\}=\{t\mid t\in
 z\}=z. Contradiction.

Lemma: If x\in On, y\subseteq x, y\neq\emptyset, then \exists_{a\in y}\forall_{b\in y}. a\in b \vee a = b.

Proof. By the foundation axiom, we get an a\in y such that a\cap y=\emptyset. Take any b\in y. b\not\in a, because a\cap y = \emptyset. By linearity of x therefore a\in b\vee a = b.

Lemma: If a is a set of ordinals, then \bigcap a is an ordinal.

Proof. We first prove that \bigcap a is an ordinal number. If x\in\bigcap a, then \forall_{b\in a}, x\in b, therefore \forall_{b\in a}, x\subseteq b, therefore x\subseteq\bigcap
 a. We still have to prove that \in is a well-ordering on \bigcap a. Irreflexivity follows from the foundation axiom: No set may contain itself. For linearity, consider b,c\in\bigcap
 a, that is, b\in d, c\in d for all d\in a. Since d is an ordinal, linearity holds for b,c. Well-foundedness of \in follows from the foundation axiom. Transitivity is left as an exercise.

Chaining a few more technical proofs, we could prove:

Theorem: For any two a,b\in On, we have a\in b\vee a=b\vee
b\in a.

Corollary: Every set of ordinals is well-ordered by the \in relation.

We can generalize induction on \mathbb{N} to induction on On:

Theorem (Transfinite Induction): If for some proposition P we have P(\emptyset), and \forall y\in On.(\forall x\in
  y. P(x))\rightarrow P(y), then \forall x\in On. P(x).

Proof. Assume not. Then there is some x\in On with \neg
 P(x), and therefore \{y\le x\mid\neg P(y)\} is a well-orderet set and has a minimum \alpha, which is also the absolute minimum value with \neg P(\alpha). Trivially, \alpha\neq\emptyset, and by its minimality, also \forall
 x\in\alpha P(x), but this would imply P(\alpha). Contradiction.

Lemma: On is not a set.

Proof. If On was a set, On\in On. Contradiction.

Lemma: Every well-ordering (A,<) is isomorphic to some ordinal number.

Proof Sketch. Define f(\emptyset) = \min A. Now let f be defined for all \alpha\in\beta. If there is still an m\in
 A remaining, set f(\beta):=m. Otherwise, proceed. Since we assumed that A is a set, this procedure must terminate at some point.

The nice thing is that in this theory we have concrete objects to talk about, namely the ordinal numbers.

Zorn's Lemma

Zorn's Lemma is one of the three classically equivalent axioms independent of ZF: The well-ordering theorem, which says that every set has some well-ordering; the axiom of choice; and Zorn's Lemma. It is probably the one that is used most often explicitly outside of set theory.

Zorn's Lemma: If (P, <) is transitive, reflexive and every non-empty chain has an upper bound, then P contains a maximal element.

Notice: A maximal element might not be comparable with many other elements.

Definition: A Well-quasi-ordering is a well-ordering except for it may be nonlinear.

In some sense this generalizes the notion of trees. Zorn's Lemma can be reduced to some stronger property about well-quasi-orders:

Theorem: If (P, <) is transitive, reflexive and every non-empty well-ordered subset has an upper bound, then for all x\in P, P contains a maximal element which is comparable to x.

This essentially sais that if every branch of the tree is bounded, then there are leaves.

(Linear) Algebra

A vector space (V, +, \cdot) over a field F is defined by a few axioms that can easily be looked up in wikipedia.

Theorem: Every vector space has a base.

Proof 1. Take an arbitrary element. If the hull of the element is the whole space, you are done. Otherwise, take an element which is not in the hull and proceed. As the vector space is a set, this process must "end" after infinitely many steps: After "set" many steps.

Proof 2. All chains of bases are bounded. Therefore, by ZL, there is a basis.

Proof 1 is normally only done in the finite case, but also works in the infinite case, because of transfinite induction. Proof 2 uses Zorn's Lemma. Similarily, algebraic closure and many other theorems use Zorn's Lemma.

Fun Fact: The groups (\mathbb{R}, +) and (\mathbb{C},
+) are isomorphic.

Proof. It is easy to show that both are vector spaces over \mathbb{Q}, and as such, they have a countable base.

Recursion Theory

Consider a simple programming language: You have an arbitrary number of registers a[i] which are initially 0 and can store natural numbers. You have a command a[i]++ which increments the register a[i], and a[i]-- which decrements it if it is not 0. (We do not allow constructs like a[a[i]], the i must be constants.) You have an exit command. Furthermore, you have a command if a[i] == 0 then goto l1 where l1 is the line number to jump to. It is easy to show that this language is turing complete. So especially, it is generally undecidable, whether a program terminates.

However, we can change the semantics a bit: Attach every program line with an additional function f from ordinal numbers into ordinal numbers (or, if you want to implement it on a real computer, other well-orderings), which must satisfy the condition that it is strictly sublinear, that is, f\alpha < \alpha for all \alpha>0. In the beginning, you start with some ordinal number, that will, at every step, be decreased through the corresponding function. The program terminates on exit as before, or as soon as the ordinal is 0.

All programs in such a language terminate. What programs can be expressed depends on the values of the original ordinal number that we allow. By the way, this is not pure theory.