External Content not shown. Further Information.
Nerd Culture:
Science:
Software, Hardware:
Zeroth World:
Comics/Images/Audios/Videos/Games/Art:
External Content not shown. Further Information.
Popular Culture:
Nerd Culture:
Software, Hardware:
Zeroth World:
Comics/Images/Audios/Videos/Games/Art:
Quotes:
And again, a talk for the best mathematics club of the multiverse. This time, I thought I'd have a slightly more abstract topic, namely Kripke models. As always, this is not a scientific talk, and it focuses on breadth rather than depth, and neglects formality in favour of comprehensibility. Its audience will mainly consist of young students who will probably not have experience in mathematical logic for the largest part.
Anyway, feel free to drop a comment if you notice any mistakes.
The lambda calculus is the prototype of all functional programming languages. We will give a short informal introduction to it.
A lambda term is inductively defined as
The idea of the untyped lambda calculus is that everything is a function. Functions map functions to functions. Lambda terms are the only objects one talks about.
A problem that arises from the above definition is that you might have
a lambda term . If we just replaced
, we would have
, which is obviously not what we
want. Actually, the inner
is bound by the inner
, and will not be replaced. It is possible to define
this formally, but for this talk we just forbid that this occurs.
Another problem arises when we substitute with a term that itself
contains a variable. Say, we have . This is obviously not intended, and we
forbid this to happen, instead of handling it formally.
A variable is bound in a term, when it is captured by some
lambda. It is free otherwise. A term is closed when it does not
contain free variables. For example, contains
freely, while
is a closed term.
As for most functional programming languages, we can assign types to
terms. In the simply-typed lambda calculus, there are atomic types
and arrow types, which are of the form
, where
are
types. Variables will be assigned a type. We write
to denote that the term
has the type
. The intuition is that this term is a function from objects of
type
to objects of type
. We therefore define the
typing rule
. Furthermore, we only allow
applications when the types fit, that is,
. Of course, we can leave
out type annotations when they are clear or not important. This is a
very simple type system, but most other type systems are based on
this.
We now ask ourselves the question whether there is a closed term of
type . Well, of
course there is none, otherwise we wouldn't ask. Kripke models are a
way of answering this kind of questions.
We are given a rooted tree , where
is the set of
nodes, and
is the "is parent" relation for
this tree. The tree need not be finite.
Now, for every atomic type , let a monotone function
be given, that is,
.
A triple is called a Kripke model (well, at least a
very simple form of a Kripke model). We now define a so-called
forcing relation
(where
is the set of simple types).
We define
We say that ("
models
") if and only if
.
Lemma (Monotonicity): Let be a Kripke model, and
with
, and
be some type. If
, then
.
Proof: We prove this by structural induction on . If
for some atomic type
, this holds by the
monotonicity of
.
Now Let , and assume
, that is, for all
,
implies
. But then the same
holds especially forall
, hence
.
Q.E.D.
Lemma (Correctness): Let a closed simply-typed lambda term
exist. Then every model
satisfies
.
Proof: We slightly generalize the Lemma. We actually prove: If
there exists a term with free variables
, then for every
,
if we have
for all
, we also
have
. We prove this by structural
induction.
Our induction hypothesis is that the current entailment holds for
all Kripke models. Notice that if , then
is (trivially) also a Kripke model.
Obviously, it holds for variables .
Assume , where
has the free variables
and
has the free
variables
(notice that
both sets of free variables need not be disjoint). Assume that for all
we have
. Then by induction,
we have
and
. But
means that
implies
. Hence, the claim follows.
Assume , and
. Besides
, let
have the free variables
, and
let again
for all
. We now
have to show that
implies
for all
. By our monotonicity
lemma,
implies
. By our induction hypothesis for
is that this
holds for all Kripke models, especially for
. Hence, for all
,
implies
. Therefore,
, and therefore,
.
Q.E.D.
Now that we have shown correctness, we can answer our above question.
Lemma: There is no closed simply-typed lambda term of type
.
Proof: Consider the tree of words matching the regular expression
0*1?
. Define ,
and
. That is:
⋮ P→1 Q→0 001 000 P→0 Q→0 \ / P→1 Q→0 01 00 P→0 Q→0 \ / 0 P→0 Q→0
Let for some node . That
means that
implies
. For
every
, there is some
such that
but
, and therefore
, and therefore,
. So for all
,
, and therefore, for all
,
regardles of whether or not
. But
then again, if
, we have
, so
does not imply
. Therefore, our Kripke model does not force
. According to our correctness lemma,
there cannot be a closed lambda term with this type.
Q.E.D.
This example is called the Peirce formula. You might wonder why this
is interesting. In fact, it is just an introductory example. However,
if you know functional programming languages, especially Scheme,
you might be familiar with the concept of continuations. The type of
call/cc
is the Peirce formula. In Haskell's standard library,
there is also a callCC
routine with a similar type. However,
this routine has a slightly different type: It uses the
continuation translation of (see the type constructor
cont
). The reason is that Haskell is pure, and in a pure setting, it
is not possible to derive the Peirce formula, which can be shown in a
similar way as we just did.
So far, our lambda terms only have atomic types and arrow types. We add a few new type constructors:
There are additional axiomatic lambda terms for all types
:
if … then … else …
.Except for the empty type, all of these are concepts that occur similarily in most modern programming languages, maybe written in a somewhat less intuitive way. We can give terms that do simple stuff like
From that perspective, empty types make no sense: They have no
computational content. However, we can as well interpret these types
as predicates: The atomic types become atomic predicates,
will mean
"or"
,
will mean
"implies"
, and
will mean
"and"
. In this interpretation,
is the predicate that
is always wrong, and
means "not
". We therefore define the abbrevitation
. In this interpretation, closed lambda terms
become formal proofs. For example, we can prove the introduction of
contraposition:
However, the other direction cannot be derived. We can show this with
a slightly extended definition of Kripke Models: We have to add
interpretations for ,
and
:
The above proof of correctness can be extended, but it is more technical. We will therefore not do this here. In this system, the Peirce formula is not derivable as well, as can be shown by the same Kripke model as above. Also, in the same Kripke model as above, contraposition and the law of excluded middle do not hold (exercise).
We now extend our type system with objects and relations. We
define a special type of objects. A relation is a
"type with object arguments". For example, the set theoretic
-relation is a relation with two object arguments. Remember,
we are in metatheory, the object type is not specified and must be
defined by axioms.
To get the full mathematical strength, we need to introduce quantors:
The type is similar to
, and
is similar to
, except that
may depend on
.
Introducing a universal quantifier is therefore done by abstraction
, and it is eliminated
by application
.
The introduction of an existential quantifier reflects sum
introduction: . Its elimination is
where
must not occur freely in
.
We now have the full expressivity of first-order predicate logic. For
example, we can prove :
However, as before the type system we just defined only allows for intuitionistic logic. The advantage of intuitionistic logic is that if you prove the existence of something, you get an algorithm that calculates it. The disadvantage is that things that cannot be calculated cannot be shown to exist. The following is the so-called Drinker formula (or Drinker problem, or sometimes Drinker paradox):
It is not derivable in intuitionistic logic. We can show this using a Kripke model, but we first have to extend our semantic:
Firstly, every node gets a domain
of
objects, such that
. The
relation now depends on an assignment
,
which is a function from object variables
to
elements of the domain of the corresponding node. For every relation
with
arguments, now,
becomes a
function
. This corresponds
to our former function in the sense that predicates become relations
with zero arguments. We then say
if and only if
. For
, the definition is
similar to our former definition, where
decomposes to
and
.
For the interpretation of the quantors, we must define
, which is
, except for the variable
, where it is
:
We again omit the correctness proof. But we show that the Drinker
formula cannot be derivable. We set with the
canonical ordering. We set
and
for
. (This
model is taken from here.)
⋮ 3 D={0,1,2,3} b={0→1,1→1,2→1,3→0} | 2 D={0,1,2} b={0→1,1→1,2→0} | 1 D={0,1} b={0→1,1→0} | 0 D={0} b={0→0}
We set . Obviously, if
, then
. However,
, but
. Therefore,
.
A similar concept for first-order logic you might see is the concept of Beth models. Their definition is slightly different but similar, and their properties are similar. See here for example.
There is a generalization of Kripke models, the so-called presheaf
models. Here, the domains are given by a presheaf
on a
category
.
For every relation with
arguments and every object
from
we have an interpretation
such that if there is a morphism
in
, we have
. An assignment is, as
before, a map from variable symbols into objects. The definition is
now similar to the one for Kripke models: For relations, we define
. For implications we
define
if and only if for
every morphism
,
implies
.
It is also possible to define this (even more general) in terms of morphisms between classical models instead of explicitly giving interpretations for all relations and domains. You might also find a more intricate version of implication for arrow types, a version that includes computational content, as an interpretation of type theory.
A Kripke model is a special case where is a poset.
The following part is kept very short and only for older audiences. Paul Joseph Cohen proved that the continuum hypothesis is independent of Zermelo-Fraenckel Set Theory (ZFC). He uses a concept inspired by Kripke models. We will only look at the parts related to Kripke models here. For an explanation of the proof see here, here and here.
This is a relative consistency result, so we can assume that there is
a classical transitive countable model of ZFC. (It can be
proved that the existence of such a set is unprovable, by Gödel's
second incompleteness theorem.)
That is a set for which the ZFC axioms hold when relativizing
all quantors to it (that is, replacing
with
, etc). Transitivity means that
. This can be proved by the
Löwenheim-Skolem theorem and the Mostowsky collapse lemma.
We write if the formula
holds in
when relativizing all quantors to it. Notice that we already
used the character
for Kripke models. It is generally
used for semantic entailment.
is a so-called classical
model, while Kripke models are intuitionistic models.
A forcing poset is a triple completely
defined in
where
is a preorder with the largest
element
and the splitting condition that for all
there exist
such that there is no
, that is, they form no diamond, that is, the ordering is
similar to a tree.
A -name is, roughly speaking, a set with an element
of
attached, in which every element itself is a
-name. That is, for example,
for
.
We define , the valuation map.
We now define
where is the set of
-names in
. We now define a forcing relation on elements of
.
One can show that if satisfies some conditions,
holds there is a
such that
.
External Content not shown. Further Information.
Popular Culture:
Nerd Culture:
Science:
Software, Hardware:
Zeroth World:
Comics/Images/Audios/Videos/Games/Art:
(but thanks to the power of free software, this has been fixed already!)
External Content not shown. Further Information.
I had some server problems recently. I hope everything works again.
Popular Culture:
Science, Software, Hardware:
Comics/Images/Audios/Videos/Games/Art:
Quotes:
External Content not shown. Further Information.
Sorry, I have no time for regular updates and comics currently. But new comics will follow soon.
Popular Culture:
Nerd Culture:
Science, Software, Hardware:
Zeroth World:
Comics/Images/Audios/Videos/Games/Art:
Quotes: